- ... trees1
- As distinct from resolution
proof trees where the emphasis is on what objects participate in each
step of the proof. We elide such details here as the emphasis is on
searching through the intermediate (ground) results of a proof to identify
faulty clauses in the theory (Section 2).
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... language2
- Once we allow such objects
in the hypothesis space, we have all sorts of computability issues to
deal with. For example, it is no longer the case that the process of
checking that the theory entails the observations necessarily
terminates.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... viewpoint3
- Prior to
Kant, that is.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ...
them4
- Obviously there are plenty of technical caveats if this is to
go through: for example, the observations must completely characterise the
target set, which is required to be describable in some formalism (in
other words, it must be at least recursively enumerable).
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ...5
- In
less logical language, MIS assumes that the user has an intuitive idea
of or can empirically verify the ground facts in . Loosely, the
collection of these facts is termed a model, and the point of
this exercise is to find a set of clauses that describes the model.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
- ... way6
- Indeed, if a theory contains a contradiction then it contains
every statement in .
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.